I often write on this blog about evidence-based policy, but I
want to write this week about how I feel torn in relation to this issue.
I was reminded of the ‘evidence-based’ phrase as I saw responses
to the
Government’s new drug strategy and the
release of the latest drug-related death figures. Transform,
Release,
Alex
Stevens and others stated that the government was ‘ignoring’ evidence.
But on a quick Google search, I can’t see that Amber Rudd or
Sarah Newton particularly used this phrase.
I’m not saying they didn’t use it at all, or that they wouldn’t want to
make this claim – Sarah Newton did challenge the idea of decriminalisation on
the basis that: ‘When you look
at all the other available evidence, we just don't agree.’ I’d just suggest that they weren’t quite
using the same ‘evidence based policy’ frame for their arguments.
On the
Home Office webpage launching the strategy, the only reference to
‘evidence’ comes from Paul Hayes,
which probably says more about the discourses of lobbyists and policy
commentators than politicians. As Alex
Stevens’ own research would predict, the politicians were more interested
in appearing ‘tough’ on ‘dangerous drugs’, as Sarah Newton put it in that
article for DDN.
I should of course make my standard statement that when people
cite evidence, it’s usually in relation to one ‘outcome’ of concern – in this
case, drug-related deaths. There is
indeed good evidence that things like purity testing, drug consumption rooms,
prescribed heroin, retention in treatment etc all reduce drug-related deaths
(DRDs). The problem of course comes when
you acknowledge that DRDs aren’t the only outcome policymakers might be
interested in (and they’re not the only drug-related outcome we should be
interested in).
Regardless of our feelings about them, policymakers have
other legitimate concerns: for example they worry that certain initiatives
might undermine the fall in young people using substances. That is, that decriminalisation or drug
consumption rooms, or pill testing might send
out the ‘wrong message’. Giving them
the benefit of the doubt, this could be genuine concern regarding harm
reduction, as much as appearing ‘tough’.
(As an aside, it’s interesting that many of those who
campaign on alcohol policy in the name of ‘public health’ would prefer to see
fewer people using alcohol on the basis of the population model of
alcohol-related harm, whereas those who campaign on policy relating to other
drugs under the same banner often see no issue with more people using, and
focus entirely on ‘harm’.)
But, more importantly, this isn’t just about harm reduction
and drug-related deaths. It’s also about
morality. You might think it shouldn’t
be, but all politics is about morality.
Housing policy, inheritance tax, unemployment benefit – we can use
‘evidence’ in these arguments, and use economic theory to argue that putting a
pound in the pocket of someone on £20,000 a year will benefit the economy more
than putting it in the pocket of a millionaire, but that can’t be the end of
the argument. There will still be a
discussion about whether that person ‘deserves’ that money. And this is an important and necessary debate
– because no matter which side of the political fence you sit, there are times
when the ‘evidence’ for some perceived positive effect simply cannot outweigh
the moral distaste you feel for a position.
And there’s the broader slippery slope argument: even if you don’t
oppose this specific measure, it dilutes a point of principle that makes later
distasteful initiatives more likely.
Here, we can see quite quickly how this applies to all parts
of the political spectrum. Peter
Hitchens is quite open that his position on ‘drugs’ isn’t simply about the
objective ‘harm’ they cause; it’s that taking intoxicants is
somehow ‘wrong’. And for all that
left-liberals often like to think they’re wholly swayed by evidence, the
‘evidence’ would suggest otherwise and in fact ‘the
Labour Party is a moral crusade or it is nothing’. Finally, libertarians like Chris Snowdon
often make use of the
slippery slope argument. For
perfectly legitimate reasons, we don’t simply judge individual initiatives by
their specific impacts on one outcome.
And most commentators on drug policy accept this – or at least
are resigned to it.
Now here’s where I feel slightly torn. My view on this blog is typically that we
should acknowledge the complexity of policymaking and evaluation, and even then
not discount the importance of moral or political positions; policymaking can’t
simply be technocracy (even if we wanted it to be).
But then when it comes down to it, this can make me feel
uncomfortable. That is, the whole point
of this blog is to encourage careful, nuanced thinking, and question
black-and-white thinking, when most of life is more complicated than that. Unfortunately, a critique of the
‘evidence-based’ position can somehow lead to an equally absolutist position of
‘anything goes’. That is completely at
odds with the aim of ‘thinking
to some purpose’, as anything goes requires no thought at all.
What I mean is: even if the root cause of your position is
irrational, or personal, you need to be able to articulate and explain it,
maybe by saying that a certain policy is just a moral red line for you, or it
just feels wrong, and describe why. That
isn’t to devalue the point; just to explain it.
And this this can sometimes be difficult and
uncomfortable. That thinking process
shouldn’t simply be about saying ‘I think it so it’s reasonable’; it’s about
reflecting on why you react in a particular way, and explaining it to someone
else.
But when we acknowledge that, as the New Yorker article I
linked to put it, ‘facts don’t change our minds’, this can open a can of worms.
As a response by a communications professional to a recent
Guardian article put it: ‘telling
people you’re wrong doesn’t work’.
This is generally true (although often not in a professional context,
where in my experience we all seem much happier to look at evidence and change
our minds), but the complexity is illustrated by the fact that the author –
Nicky Hawkins – gives examples of successful campaigns that actually did exactly
that: telling people they were wrong.
She explains how drink driving campaigns persuaded people that the issue
wasn’t simply about ‘drunk’ drivers as much as the fact that anyone with a
certain blood alcohol level will have slower reactions and poorer
coordination. That wasn’t just a way to
justify the campaigns; it was the actual aim.
Deaths on the roads aren’t just caused by ‘alcoholics’.
But here’s where the difficulty arises. The other example given is the justification
for the smoking ban, where the villain of the piece became (apparently)
second-hand smoke, not smokers themselves.
I don’t want to go into this in too much detail, partly because plenty
of readers will know this example better than me. But suffice to say…
(1) the timing of this campaign made it easier: there were
fewer smokers, with rates particularly low amongst affluent/influential groups,
so that even if smokers saw this as a personal attack they weren’t a majority
or in a great position to make their voices heard. (Of course the tobacco companies were in a
strong position, but the argument wasn’t framed in relation to them, and their
credibility amongst the general public was pretty low at this point.)
(2) The apparently desirable effects weren’t just about
second-hand smoke; they were about persuading current smokers to give up.
So this wasn’t simply a brilliant campaign; the context is
crucial, and there was some selective truth-telling (if that’s a phrase) in the
accompanying justification.
There are lots of examples of this in politics in recent
years (and actually, forever), so it’s a bit odd for a communications
professional to offer this as a great insight.
Two recent classic examples prompted
me to start this blog: drug treatment isn’t actually about crime and blood
borne viruses, and tuition fees aren’t actually about getting students to pay
their own way. (The latter one is
particularly egregious, because the burden to the taxpayer is not reduced,
despite the popular narrative.)
I’m not saying the smoking ban was a bad idea, but I think
it’s a classic case of not ‘thinking to some purpose’. If the aim was to reduce passive smoking,
then there are all sorts of options other than a ban that would have been
workable.
And it’s much easier to ask people not to harm others than
it is to suggest they should behave differently to stop harming
themselves. Interestingly, the same
applies to the drink driving campaign: the most powerful point is that you
could hurt someone else, who is innocent or your ‘vice’.
Most of the key public health debates today, though, are
about people’s own decisions. Perhaps
the best way to frame these is, again, in terms of the structure that shapes
these decisions: licensing, labelling, regulation, pricing. But if the communications is designed for the
general public, to directly change their decision-making, then unfortunately
ideas of ‘passive drinking’ and the like have proved much less convincing; the
argument is still about stopping people doing harm to themselves.
I know I’d be mistaken in hoping for some kind of Habermasian perfect
communication and debate, and that kind of unrealistic aspiration is
exactly what I try to critique on this blog.
My issue, as usual, is where to draw the line when you’re faced with a
sea of grey, rather two clear camps of ‘good’ and ‘bad’.
The reason this has particularly resonated with me in the
past couple of weeks isn’t just the fact that these three releases/articles
have occurred; it’s also that I heard in my professional capacity that,
pre-figuring the words of the breastfeeding article, public health
professionals need to change the way they communicate with the public. This sounds reasonable, and personally I’m
not a fan of the preaching or evangelical approach – not because of its manner,
but simply because I don’t share its view of the ‘good life’. My objection isn’t the means, it’s the ends
(although I don’t think you can separate them neatly).
I’m now going to draw on two people more experienced and
intelligent than me.
I remember discussing with one academic a time that doubt
crept into their mind about public health and the power to persuade. If public health, in its attempts to compete
with, say, the tobacco industry in trying to shape people’s beliefs and
behaviour, adopts their principle of ‘persuade at almost any cost’, what makes
it better than them? That is, we have to
be very careful about defining what makes ‘social’ marketing ‘good’, and
ordinary marketing ‘evil’, as Gerard Hastings might put it.
This was a personal epiphany, but the general point isn’t a
new insight, and it has some broader – moral – implications, to bring the
discussion back to where it started: that policymaking can’t just be about
technocracy.
And so to reference the other wiser head: James Nicholls (amongst others) has
previously drawn attention to the role of alcohol in liberal political thought. So let’s lookmat the nineteenth-century
debate between John Stuart Mill and TH Green.
(And apologies if I oversimplify or misrepresent. Go read James’ work if you want proper
political theory.) While Green felt it
was illiberal to allow people to ‘enslave’ themselves to alcohol, and therefore
recommended banning the substance, Mill rejected this argument – despite having
used it to justify the abolition of slavery.
Mill suggested instead that if we’re really concerned with people’s
moral behaviour, we shouldn’t use prohibition to shape it. Someone who is only prevented from doing
something immoral by the lack of opportunity isn’t showing moral character;
they’re in fact behaving a lot like they’re a slave to the system. The real show of moral character comes in
making the ‘right’ choices.
And this position is further strengthened by Mill’s ‘harm
principle’ that state intervention is justified when people’s actions impinge
on others. Of course in reality this is
impossible to identify: no man is an island.
But the principle stands, even if the reality is more complicated. (I can expand on this, but I think that’ll do
for the moment. Let’s just say if I do
something, it potentially increases the likelihood that you will, so my
decision isn’t entirely free of effects on others.)
So taking those two academic insights together, I feel
uncomfortable if public health is somehow looking to change its approach.
Presenting facts is reasonable: if you drink too much you’re
more likely to die earlier. And actually
evangelising is reasonable too: I believe that a longer life, full of physical
activity and clean living is more rewarding and morally more valuable than
other ways of living. (I actually
don’t.)
But mixing the two together, and persuading people to do something
for one reason (‘you’ll love it’, ‘it’ll make you happier’) when your real
reason is something else (‘the evidence suggests people will live longer and
costs to the NHS will be reduced’) is distasteful to me.
And as I outlined right at the beginning, distaste can be a
reasonable argument for rejecting a position, if explained. So here’s my explanation: my distaste is that
getting people to do the ‘right’ thing for the ‘wrong’ reasons is patronising
and, at the risk of sounding like Chris Snowdon, a ‘slippery slope’. If the current approach of public health
professionals, with either evangelism or emphasis on ‘the evidence’ is
considered patronising, wouldn’t this be even worse?
Of course you could ask: if there are two likely effects of
an intervention why wouldn’t you emphasise the more powerful one? And there might be some moments when the
evidence and the emotion neatly intersect and provide powerful arguments. But I suggest we should judge any such
intervention by a crucial question: have you actually won the argument? If you don’t care about that question, I’m
not sure we’re on the same side in any debate.
No comments:
Post a Comment